H.F. Hallett
Spinoza▓s Conception of Eternity
Mind, Vol. 37, No. 147 (July, 1928)
There is no doctrine more fundamentally determinative in Spinozism
than that of eternity and of its relations with duration and time. We may, indeed,
justly assert that the conception of eternity is the very essence of the theory
of Spinoza. It follows, therefore, that the present essay cannot but be inadequate
and selective: it must leave most essential matters for future discussion and
amplification; many, again, and some of prime importance, must be totally ignored,
if the proper limits of space are to be observed. It will be well if we can succeed
in casting doubt upon some popular misinterpretations of the conception; and
if, over and above this, a more adequate account can be suggested in outline,
and feebly supported, our work will not have been in vain. Demonstration must
await a more ample occasion.
Few philosophers have realised (though many have suspected, and
some have acted upon the suspicion) how essential it is for a thinker on ultimate
subjects to face up to the problem of time before proceeding to lesser matters.
For this is the chart and compass and rudder without which it is fatuous to venture
out of the port of facts on to the high seas of speculation. Early in his career
Spinoza made up his mind on these matters, and we find the main lines of his
doctrine of time and eternity already laid down in those Cogitata Metaphysica
which he appended to the geometrical version of Descartes▓s Principia Philosophiae
which he published in 1663. His views suffered no reversal or essential change
right down to his untimely death in 1677: not that his thoughts turned away from
such subjects; on few things, perhaps, did he meditate more often, for few things
are more often brought to the notice of the serious philosopher, whatever may
be the special direction of his inquiries, and none are more worthy of the consideration
of a great philosopher.
It is because it has not always been remembered that the order
of discovery often reverses the logical order of nature, that Spinoza▓s doctrine
has been commonly misinterpreted as purely negative. In the order of nature eternity
is prior to [283] duration, and duration prior to time; in the order of
discovery time and duration are prior to eternity. And the position is not rendered
any the more safe for the unwary by Spinoza▓s attempt to identify the order of
nature and the order of exposition by the use of the synthetic or geometrical
mode in his chief metaphysical work, the Ethica. This is, indeed, precisely
the sort of ▒snag▓ which constitutes the ▒spinosity▓ of Spinoza.
I. Duration and time.
We begin with what is more familiar to us, viz. duration.
This term is used by Spinoza much in the same way as we (distinguishing ourselves
from the mathematical physicists) use the term ▒time▓. It means persistence,
or as Spinoza expresses it: existentia, quatenus abstracte concipitur, et
tanquam quaedam quantitatis species (Eth. II. 45 Sch.), or indefinita
existendi continuatio (Eth. II. Def. 5). It is from this quantitative character
of duration that arises the notion of measuring it, which gives us time
in the Spinozistic sense; for, observing that some things persist longer than
others, and that certain motions (such as the apparent motion of the sun round
the earth, or that of the moon, or the swing-swang of the pendulum) are regularly
recurrent, we find it convenient to take the durations thus marked off as standards
by which to measure the durations of things. Such measurements are only conventionally
absolute, but really relative, for the standard is itself a quantity, and is,
therefore, as measurable as any other quantity. Time is for Spinoza the measurement
of duration by such comparisons (Cog. Met. I. 4; Eth. II. 44 Cor. 1); it
follows immediately that time is not a real thing, but a mental tool. It cannot
belong to the Real because it is a mere measure, and its standard is arbitrary.
It is an ens rationis, a mode of thinking, or rather of imagining (i.e.,
misthinking) duration. It is an auxilium Imaginationis (Ep. 12). Nor can
there be an absolute measure of duration, for absolute measure implies an absolute
unit; but such a unit cannot be found in the duration of any existing thing,
for that duration is indefinite. The duration of a thing is not proportioned
to its absolute nature, but depends upon vicissitude; it may be long or short
as the circumstances of its occurrence determine. In the absence of obstruction
each thing would endure for ever. In the absence of its producing cause the duration
of a thing cannot even begin. Here, therefore, no absolute unit can be found.
Nor can it be found in the nature of duration itself, for duration is neither
discrete nor is it a whole. It provides for itself no absolute units either in
the [284] form of minima or in that of a maximum. Every duration,
however small, is a duration, and therefore divisible. Every duration, however
large, is partial, and therefore multipliable. But in the absence of an absolute
unit of measurement, time as a single absolute measure of duration cannot belong
to the Real.
But what of duration itself, the indefinita existendi continuatio,
can this not be predicated of the Real?
Two distinguishable, but not altogether separable arguments may
be extracted from Spinoza▓s discussions of this important point.
(1) In the first place, duration is existence quatenus
abstracte concipitur, et tanquam quaedam quantitatis species, and this quantity
is conceived as divisible. But the Real cannot be divided, for it must be self-complete
and without limit. An incomplete reality is incompletely real. Nullum substantiae
attributum potest vere concipi, ex quo sequatur, substantiam posse dividi
(Eth. I. 12). For if it were divided the sections would either be the same as
the whole (and therefore not sections at all), or different from the whole (and
therefore incapable of being produced from it merely by division), or again,
nothing real at all (which is absurd, since the Real cannot be wholly composed
of unreal sections).
Now it might be objected that whatever may be the value of these
arguments they apply not only to duration but also to extension, and yet Spinoza
retains extension as an attribute of the Real, but rejects duration. Mr Alexander
has, indeed, objected to this procedure and has suggested a renovation of the
Spinozistic theory in which duration would be retained as one of the infinite
attributes of Substance (Spinoza and Time, 1921). Spinoza himself, we
may be confident, had he been compelled to agree with the arguments in question,
would have rejected extension with duration, rather than have accepted duration
as an ultimate attribute of Substance coordinate with extension. But he would
not have recognised the dilemma, for he holds that we need not conceive extension
as divisible, though in imperfect thinking we more easily do so. Si autem
ad ipsam prout in intellectu est attendimus... quod difficillime fit,
tum, ...infinita, unica, et indivisibilis reperietur (Eth. I. 15 Sch.).
And this is the true view of extension: Quare ii prorsus garriunt, ne dicam
insaniunt, qui Substantiam Extensam ex partibus, sive corporibus ab invicem realiter
distinctis, conflatum esse putant. Perinde enim est, ac si quis ex sola
additione et coacervatione multorum circulorum quadratum, aut triangulum, aut
quid aliud, tota essentia diversum, conflare studeat (Ep. 12). Nor need we [285]
concentrate our attention solely on the intellectual conception of extension
in order to realise that it cannot be composed of sections (i.e., of extended
sections, for the term ⌠unextended section of extension■ involves a contradiction),
for even finite magnitudes may be incommensurable (i.e., incapable of
commeasurement in terms of a single unit: Spinoza gives the example of the variations
in the distance between the circumferences of two eccentric circles one of which
lies wholly within the other). A finite, divided, discrete extension is an illusion
of the imagination; but in removing the illusion we do not lose extension itself,
or even its quantitative character; but we find that the conception of an infinite,
single, indivisible extension involves no contradiction, and may be accepted
as real.
It has not always been realised, or not sufficiently, that the
contention of Spinoza is that this correction is impossible with duration conceived
as a quantity, for duration is essentially divided, for it is characterised by
the irreversible distinction of past and future, or its equivalent. If the Real
endures then its existence is always essentially divided into what has already
occurred and what has yet to occur. If that distinction implied no real division
it would be a mere distinction of reason and not the real character of duration
which we must affirm it to be. Nor does the fact that the line of division moves
steadily towards the future render the division less fatal, for every instant
is in turn the division of past and future, and to heal the breach at one place
is identical with the creation of it at the next or at another. Division and
duration appear and disappear together.
Briefly, the reason why extension survives the process of intellectual
criticism and is admitted as an attribute of Substance, while duration is excluded,
is that temporal relations are essentially asymmetrical in a sense and to a degree
in which spatial relations are not. The latter demand no special (or spatial)
variety in their terms, while the former can only be sustained in so far as periods
differ from one another in date or epoch as well as in distance from one another.
They must differ in temporal quality as well as in temporal quantity; only thus
can they be in succession. Remove the distinctions of past and future, earlier
and later, before and after, and you remove the essential character of any kind
of duration, and all that is left is a neutral form of externality like a dimension
of space. But duration is like extension in one feature only, viz. its
quantitativeness or measurability (avoiding the question as to which of these
terms is the best expression of the common quality); in its specific quality
it is [286] wholly different: a fact which is too often slurred over in
modern speculations, especially of the mathematico-physical type.
(2) These considerations lead naturally to the second and
connected set of objections to the predicating of duration of the Real.
The qualitative variety of an enduring being is a successive variety.
Whether we think of crude perceived duration with its distinctions of past, present,
and future, or of historical time with its distinctions of before and after (and
Spinoza, recognizing both, argues mainly against the latter, the former being
obviously inapplicable, to the Real), there is no getting rid of succession without
getting rid of duration. For without change there can be no duration, and without
succession no change. But change cannot be predicated of the Real, which can
lack nothing and can surrender nothing. In the being of Substance nihil prius
nec posterius dari potest (Cog. Met. II. 1); in aeterno non datur
quando, ante, nec post (Eth. I. 33 Sch. 2); and future, past, and
present are all one to Ratio, i.e., for adequate knowledge (Eth.
IV. 62).
Hence the existence of the Real cannot be an enduring existence,
not even an existence enduring without beginning or end (Eth. I. Def. 8).
How, then, is the existence of the Real to be construed? It is
not a quantity measurable by time. It does not endure: its existence is not divisible
into earlier and later stages. But neither is it momentary. That was a strange
misconception expressed by M. Bergson in one of his earlier works, that
for Spinoza ⌠la durée indéfinie des choses tenait toute entière
dans un moment unique, qui est l▓éternité■ (Les Données
Immédiates, ch. 3), but comparable with that even commoner opinion that
for Spinoza all multiplicity fades into mere identity in Substance, and all content
into vacuity; but for Spinoza, we must contend, the Real occupies neither one
moment, nor many moments, nor even infinite moments. God does not exist ab
aeterno, for that would imply a duration than which no longer can be conceived;
He does not exist in a moment, for that would imply a duration than which no
shorter can be conceived; and both are impossible, talis enim est natura durationis,
ut semper major et minor data possit concipi (Cog. Met. II. 10).
Must we conclude, then, that what does not exist in one, many,
or infinite moments of duration does not exist at all? By no means; there can
be no doubt whatsoever that Spinoza himself draws, and could draw, no such conclusion.
No one has ever doubted that he at least attempts to establish a [287] species
of existence beyond the limitations of duration and time, though many have asserted
or implied that he has failed to do so. Such existence beyond the limitations
of duration he calls an eternal existence, and in the space that remains to us
we must attempt an explanation and discussion of some of the interpretations
which have been put upon this conception, and make some tentative suggestions
of our own.
II. Eternity.
ї1.
There is a short and easy way of interpreting Spinoza▓s conception
of an eternal existence which, though in itself wholly unsatisfactory, and as
applied to Spinoza easily refuted, yet must be mentioned, both because it is
the common interpretation, and also because it has some apparent basis in expressions
used here and there by Spinoza himself. The reading to which we refer is not
precisely that which takes eternity as synonymous with necessity, but one which,
realising that necessity is at most the logical proprium of an eternal
existence and not its metaphysical essence, attempts to construe the existence
which is eternal as equivalent to, or framed on the analogy of, the being which
belongs to necessary truths such as the propositions of Euclid or established
scientific generalisations. And prima facie there is some evidence for
that view in Spinoza▓s own expressions; the Explanation, for example, which is
added to the definition of Eternity at the beginning of the first part of the
Ethica, seems to bear this significance: Talis enim existentia ut aeterna
veritas, sicut rei essentia, concipitur, and one has to get well within the
mind of Spinoza before it becomes clear how little such words bear the meaning
we are prone to attach to them. For eternal truths, as we use the phrase, do
not exist at all as such, they hold, or ▒subsist,▓ as the phrase runs nowadays.
That is so because they are abstractions; in Hume▓s useful phrase, they are ▒relations
of ideas▓ and not ▒matters of fact.▓ They may be true of existence, they are
not themselves existences.
Now Spinoza▓s point of view is essentially different, and, though
remote from both, nearer to that of Plato than to that of Empiricism. For him
as for Plato to know truly is to know the real; an eternal truth is in fact the
same thing as an eternal reality. It is not an abstract universal, or the connexion
of abstract universals. That is the point of the [288] last part of the
sentence we quoted: aeterna veritas, sicut rei essentia. He speaks elsewhere
of the essence of a man as an eternal truth (Eth. I. 17 Sch.), and the first
Corollary to Eth. I. 20 runs: Hinc sequitur...Dei existentiam,
sicut ejus essentiam, aeternam esse veritatem. To a correspondent who asked
him point blank whether things and their modifications are eternal truths, he
answered: Omnino. Si regeris, cur eas aeternas veritates non voco?
respondeo, ut eas distinguant, uti omnes solent ab iis, quae nullam rem reive
affectionem explicant, ut ex. gr. a nihilo nihil fit (Ep. 10).
An eternal existence, therefore, must not be explained, or explained
away, as framed on the analogy of the validity of abstract or universal scientific
principles or mathematical truths. For the whole paraphernalia of abstract universals
of whatever kind had been definitely relegated to Imaginatio, of knowledge
of the lowest, most confused, and emptiest kind, resulting rather from impotence
than from the power of the mind (cf. Eth. II. 40 Sch. 1). Possumus
videre, apprime nobis esse necessarium, ut semper a rebus physicis, sive ab entibus
realibus, omnes nostras ideas deducamus, progrediendo, quo ad ejus fieri potest,
secundum seriem causarum ab uno ente reali ad aliud ens reale, et ita quidem,
ut ad abstracta et universalia non transeamus, sive ut ab iis aliquid reale non
concludamus, sive ut ea ab aliquo reali non concludantur: utrumque enim
verum progressum intellectus interrumpit (De Intell. Emend., Op. Post., p. 388).
Spinoza▓s own theory of Ratio (the Second Kind of Knowledge)
is based upon a new kind of abstraction in which universal principles are embodied
in universal particulars, and truths of reason are no longer mere ▒relations
of ideas▓ but also and essentially relations of existences, infinite and eternal.
Truth is never a mere relation of ideas thought of as pictures or images in the
mind; for an idea is the objective essence of a thing, and to have an idea is
to know a thing, while to have a true idea is to apprehend reality. The eternity
of scientific truths, therefore, rightly conceived, i.e. as truths about
universal particulars, and not mere hypotheses, is not definable by negation
as timelessness simpliciter, but as existence of a certain kind. The assertion
that it is the nature of Ratio to conceive things sub quadam specie
aeternitatis must not be interpreted as if its objects were ▒ideal contents▓
or ▒floating ideas▓ applying at any point of time because independent of time-reference;
its objects are particular existences which are also universal because they are
coextensive with all being. [289]
ї2.
Before we proceed to a direct exposition of Spinoza▓s conception
of eternity, it will be well to consider as briefly as possible the notion of
eternal existence as equivalent to enduring existence purged from those elements
which incapacitate it for survival in the Real. Those features are, as we have
seen, divisibility and successiveness. The former imperfection is shared by extension
as it is uncritically apprehended by Imaginatio; the latter, which implies
the former, though eminenter, is peculiar to duration. The question now
is, therefore, whether eternity must not be that attribute of the Real which
remains when the offending successiveness has been removed from duration. Without
succession there can be, of course, no duration; but may there not remain a non-durational
form of existence which is eternity?
The probable argument would be that the successiveness which infects
an enduring existence is relative only to this or that observer or experient,
and is his subjective addition, (or rather, subtraction) from the eternal co-existent
facts. Existence, it would be argued, purged from these subjective, ambiguities
is not a successive existence, and does not endure in any objectionable sense
of that term; but for analytic thought, as for selective perception, features
of the eternal whole may be apprehended successively; and though perception presents
them in an irreversible order, analytic thought can order them according to its
special requirements. In, other words, eternity on this view is the fourth dimension
of the mathematical physicists, and is, or ought to be, indistinguishable from
any of the dimensions of space. In it there is no present, past, or future. Nor
are these simply replaced, as in Absolute Time, by the relations of before and
after. In passing from the subjective perspective of duration to an objective
▒time▓ by the removal of the point of reference given by the observer▓s ▒now,▓
we must pass also from an irreversible time to a neutral order which may be read
according to the special needs of the thinker. Subjective duration moves from
past to future, or, adopting the point of view of the experient, future moves
to past; but it does so because past means that which has been given,
future that which will be given, and present that which is being given.
It is natural and inoffensive to begin with what we already have and are having,
and pass on to what we shall have. But in this purified objective ▒time,▓ considered
strictly as such, no such distinctions are forthcoming, [290] and they only
appear to be so because we transfer to objective ▒time▓ distinctions which are
only valid for subjective time. We imagine ourselves at a point of objective
▒time,▓ and say that what is before that is past, and what is after it is future,
and that the flow of time is from the past to the future, i.e. from before
to after. But if subjective time is unreal we have no right to transfer its direction
of flow to an objective ▒time▓ for which past, present, and future have no significance,
since in it all is given. Objective ▒time,▓ therefore, can have no direction
of flow, and the sense of duration which lurks about the terms ▒before▓ and ▒after▓
must be carefully excluded if we are to continue to use them in relation to this
purified neutral order.
Objective ▒time▓ must therefore be distinguished from that hybrid
form which commonly occupies attention in this connexion, and which is an objective
order into which, by the use of memory and imagination, we place the objects
of our immediate experience, thus determining its direction of flow, and then
proceed to fill out the earlier periods with objects lying beyond our immediate
experience but connected therewith in various ways. This is Historical Time,
which is transformed into Absolute Time by leaving out the point of reference
given by the ▒now▓ or ▒present epoch,▓ but carefully (but illegitimately) retaining
the direction of flow. In true objective ▒time▓ the distinction of realised and
unrealised disappears, and with it duration itself, and we are left with a neutral
order of externality.
No such neutral order is an adequate representation of eternity
as it is conceived by Spinoza. For though it is an order of existences, it is
not that order which characterises the Real. It suggests that the order of things
in time is, with minor corrections for the spatio-temporal perspective of the
experient, the real order of existences. But according to Spinoza we know that
it is not so. The real order is the logical order, which is not a mere corrected
temporal order, but proceeds on a different plan. There is no point to point
correspondence between events in time and the stages of logical order. No distinction
is more clear in Spinoza than that between the communis naturae ordo (Eth.
II. 29 Cor. et Sch.; 30 Dem.) and the ordo intellectus
(Eth. II. 18 Sch.) or ordo ad intellectum (Eth. II. 40 Sch.
2; V. 10) through which the actual time order of our experiences is distinguished
from the logical order of essences. It is precisely the order in which things
are conceived which determines their reality or unreality; for all things are
real and eternal in so far as they survive the process of being arranged in the
intellectual [291] order, as all things are illusory and corruptible as
objects of mere perception.
Furthermore, and in the second place, the logical order is not
neutral; it moves from essence to expression, from ground to consequent, from
Substance to mode. For Intellectus the process in time from cause to effect
gives place to the procession of grounds and consequents in eternity, and in
the same transvaluation Imaginatio, the First Kind of Knowledge, gives
place to adequate knowledge of the Second or Third Kinds. The change from time-order
to the intellectual order, therefore, is not a change to neutrality, but a change
from an order of exclusion to an order of inclusion or implication.
ї 3.
What, then, is the account which Spinoza himself gives of eternity?
The distinction between eternity and duration arises from the fact that we conceive
the existence of Substance as entirely different from the existence of modes
(Ep. 12). Eternity is an attributum, sub quo infinitam Dei existentiam concipimus,
Duratio vero est attributum, sub quo rerum creatarum existentiam, prout
in sua actualitate perseverant, concipimus (Cog. Met. I. 4). Per durationem
modorum tantum existentiam explicare possumus, Substantiae vero per aeternitatem,
hoc est, infinitam existendi, sive, invita latinitate, essendi fruitionem
(Ep. 12). Further as the duration of a thing is its whole existence (quantum
enim durationi alicujus rei detrahis, tantundem ejus existentiae detrahi necesse
est (Cog. Met. I. 4) ) so eternity is that infinita existentia which
coincides with the real essence of God (Deo actu competit) quae soli
Deo tribuenda, non vero ulli rei creatae; non, inquam, quamvis earum duratio
utroque careat fine (Cog. Met. II. 1). For this existence is not something
which is added to God, even by right; it is not something that God enjoys or,
possesses, it is the Divine Being. Deus vero non potest dici frui existentia,
nam existentia Dei est Deus ipse (loc. cit.). Duration is,
indeed, the enjoyment of existence, but eternity is existence itself.
It is this infinite realisation of existence, and not an indefinite
emptying of existence, that must give us our clue to Spinoza▓s conception of
eternity. What duration is to a conditioned existence that, or not less than
that, is eternity to the necessary existence of God; it is its essence. Ut
nullam Deo durationem tribuamus, dicimus eum esse aeternum, he says, hastily
correcting his not unconsidered assertion that we use the term eternity to explain
the duration of God (Cog. Met. II. 1). [292] We need not consider here the
reputed double use of the term duration by Spinoza; it would be easy to show
that the ambiguity belonged not to the mind of Spinoza but to duration itself;
it was essential for him both to distinguish and to relate the two conceptions:
to distinguish them, since he was very much concerned to distinguish an eternal
existence from an existence ab aeterno; to relate them, since not only
are both for him forms of existence, but they are both forms of the same aspect
of existence, for duration is clearly related to eternity in a way in which Number
(e.g.) is not. These are facts which have too often been overlooked, especially
by those who have been wont to think of the eternity of Spinoza as the mere negation
of duration, or as equivalent to timelessness.
Eternity is a kind of existence, it is existence par excellence,
an infinite existence; or, as the formal definition runs: per aeternitatem
intelligo ipsam existentiam, quatenus ex sola rei aeternae definitione necessario
sequi concipitur (Eth. I. Def. 8); that is to say, where essence and
existence are no longer distinguishable. One of Spinoza▓s great sayings, characterised
by his peculiar intensity of meaning and restraint of expression, is that in
which he lays bare the source of the errors of metaphysical writers on this subject,
as due to the fact that they attempt to explain eternity in abstraction from
the nature of God or perfect being, quasi aeternitas absque essentiae divinae
contemplatione intelligi posset, vel quid esset praeter divinam essentiam
(Cog. Met. II. 1).
It remains next for us to inquire into the peculiar nature of this
existence which is not to be conceived as a mere persistence. Have we any experience
of such a form of existence? In the absence of such experience we might well
accept as abstract conclusions the unreality of duration, and the necessity of
a certain intellectual order, but we should have no real apprehension of the
nature of eternity.
According to Spinoza we are not left without such experience: sentimus
experimurque nos aeternos esse (Eth. V. 23 Sch.), for we as men have
commerce with and enter into reality; and we do so most truly as entering into
the universal being in and through those intellectual perceptions by which our
groundedness in the Real is revealed, and our true being enjoyed. Nam mens
non minus res illas sentit, quas intelligendo concipit, quam quas in memoria
habet. Mentis enim oculi, quibus res videt observatque, sunt ipsae demonstrationes
(Eth. V. 23 Sch.) Further, as we saw before, Spinoza does not regard our
demonstrative knowledge as merely hypothetical and concerned with abstract universal
features of [293] existence, for the objects of Ratio are universal
particulars: the common properties or universal bases of all finite things; haec
fixa et aeterna, quamvis sint singularia, tamen ob eorum ubique praesentiam ac
latissimam potentiam, erunt nobis tanquam universalia, sive genera definitionum
rerum singularium mutabilium, et causae proximae omnium rerum (De Intell.
Emend., Op. Post., p. 389). Ratio no less than Scientia Intuitiva
brings us into contact with the Real, and its peculiar failing is not that it
is merely hypothetical, but that it is selective and analytic in procedure. Its
main concern is not the individual nature of these fixa et aeterna as
universal particulars, but their necessary connexions and the relations of their
constituents. Undoubtedly these connexions and relations are also constituents,
but they are conceived by Ratio for themselves and not as constituting
this or that individual. But in spite of these special limitations it is none
the less de natura Rationis res sub quadam aeternitatis specie percipere
(Eth. II. 44 Cor. 2); and the expression has a peculiar appropriateness
as applied to the mode of apprehension that belongs to Ratio. In view
of the history of the phrase, and also the fact that Spinoza applies it to Scientia
Intuitiva as well as to Ratio, it is improbable that this secondary
propriety in any way influenced him in adopting, and so often repeating, this
celebrated expression; doubtless he uses it as signifying simply ▒qua
eternal,▓ but that Ratio is capable of providing a satisfactory idea of
the nature of eternity is not suggested by Spinoza. Ratio views things
▒under the form of eternity▓ but it assumes rather than explicates the special
nature of an eternal existence. The special concern which Spinoza shows in the
proof of this Corollary to exclude all time relations (absque ulla temporis
relatione), and to emphasise the logical properties of an eternal existence,
viz. its necessity, has misled many into supposing that he intends here
to convey the metaphysical essence of eternity. We may be confident that he has
no such intention, for it is necessary to pass beyond Ratio to Scientia
Intuitiva to obtain that further knowledge; the necessary connections and
relations of things must be woven into concrete knowledge of individuals as such,
and not as mere assembled implicates. In order to experience eternal existence
we must be able to take a single view of an individual experience as it were
from inside; for thus only to know things sub quadam specie aeternitatis
is also to feel and prove nos aeternos esse. There need be, for us there
can be, no real separation of the two forms of knowledge; Ratio blossoms
into Scientia Intuitiva, which reassures itself by means of [294]
Ratio; thus our finitude genuinely reveals itself. The Ethica itself
is an example of such relations: in the main it is a system of Ratio,
but again and again it uses conceptions which imply the use of Scientia Intuitiva.
Of no part is this more true than of the second section of Part V. We might
go so far as to assert that it is precisely those propositions which most truly
exemplify the processes of Ratio that provide the text for the view of
Spinozism as reducing relation to identity and existence to a moment; as it is
the more concrete teaching of Part V. that must become the essential ground for
a true view of eternity.
ї 4.
We have said that it is to Scientia Intuitiva that we must
look for our main clue to the Spinozistic conception of eternity, but it is not
necessary, indeed it would be pernicious, to separate the second section of Part
V. of the Ethica from the rest of the work. Spinoza means to tell a single
story; and in order to show that in the main he succeeds in doing so we may consider
next the theory of the Affectus which is found in Part III. and which
has, an important bearing on our main problem.
Spinoza draws a clear distinction between the laetitia, tristitia,
and cupiditas of the finite mode, on the one hand, and the eternal beatitudo
of God and the free man. Conscious of its finitude, each fluctuating mode suffers
continual change, which it as continually resists; this change and the striving
against change are experienced as laetitia, tristitia and cupiditas.
In these affectus we are directly aware of processes, which are not to
be taken as alternating unconnected states, but rather as felt qualities in which
succession has been transcended but not lost, and in which transformation has
become a felt, and therefore direct, datum. For Spinoza is emphatic in his insistence
upon the identity of the affectus with the process and not with the termini
of the process: Dico transitionem. Nam Laetitia non est ipsa perfectio.
Si enim homo cum perfectione, ad quam transit, nasceretur, ejusdem absque
Laetitiae affectu compos esset; ... Nec dicere possumus, quod Tristitia
in privatione majoris perfectionis consistit; nam privatio nihil est,
Tristitia autem affectus actus est, qui propterea nullus alius esse potest, quam
actus transeundi ad minorem perfectionem (Eth. III. Aff. Def. III. Explic.).
In other words, the finite mind does not merely apprehend its objects and its
ideas in their logical or perceptual distinction and order, it directly apprehends
their changes towards or [295] away from perfection, and it apprehends its
own existence as a ceaseless urge or struggle against an obstructive environment.
As opposed to these direct experiences of transition
and of duration which belong to the finite mode, Spinoza contrasts the eternal
blessedness of God: si Laetitia in transitione ad majorem perfectionem consistit,
Beatitudo sane in eo consistere debet, quod mens ipsa perfectione sit praedita
(Eth. V. 33 Sch.). No assertion in the Ethica is more decisive for
our argument, for laetitia belongs to an enduring existence, but beatitude
to one which is eternal. As opposed to duration which implies change towards
or from perfection, an eternal being, incapable of change, enjoys fullness and
perfection of existence, enjoys blessedness, not as though it were something
different from its existence and essence, but as the very content of its reality.
It has sometimes been asserted that, in view of Spinoza▓s own statements
about the nature of the fundamental affectus, the conception of beatitudo,
though in itself one of the most attractive features of the system, is really
only a beautiful excrescence. For the affectus, as transitions to or from
perfection, are essentially durational in character; an eternal being, on the
contrary, being incapable of such transitions, must lack all affective experience.
We may meet that contention by tracing the development of the notion of beatitudo.
The transition to this conception from that of laetitia is through the
conception of mentis acquiescentia in se ipso, which is defined as laetitia
orta ex eo, quod homo se ipsum suamque agendi potentiam contemplatur (Eth.
III. Aff. Def. XXV.), that is to say it is not mere abstract laetitia
hut a grounded joy, a joy arising from the perception of a perfection already
possessed. Now the perfection or reality of a thing, according to Spinoza, is
identical with its activity, it is the possession within its own individual nature
of adequate genetic causes for its particular content. The essence of a thing
in so far as it is real is this activity or grounded content. Mens nostra
quaedam agit... quatenus adaequatas habet ideas eatenus quaedam necessario
agit (Eth. III. 1). The actual essence of a finite thing is this real essence
modified in proportion to its finitude by the passivity involved in inadequate
ideas. The result of this qualification or finitude is to limit existence to
the form of duration, so that the potentia of the thing appears as its
conatus in suo esse perseverare, and as cupiditas, the third fundamental
affectus. It follows that cupiditas does not belong to God for
whom actual and real essence are identical, and who therefore cannot be conceived
as enduring. These statements involve important principles which we have no space
to elaborate; for the present we [296] must be content to sum them up dogmatically
by saying that genuine activity, as it is found in God and the eternal part of
the free man, is not identical with cupiditas, and does not imply transient
causality; it is one with the logical nisus of adequate or grounded ideas.
It follows, further, from the well-known doctrine of idea ideae
that we are capable of a reflective joy in contemplating our concrete achievements,
over and above the direct joy of this or that achieving. For the mind could not
unknowingly possess this nisus to wholeness which belongs to adequate
ideas, for its being is its knowledge: nostrae Mentis essentia in sola cognitione
consista (Eth. V. 36 Sch.). Thus though it is not true to say that reflective
knowledge constitutes individuality, it is certainly the source of our
enjoyment of our individuality or perfection sub specie acquiescentiae.
The mind, therefore, not only experiences its temporal transitions as affectus,
it also knows itself, and so far as it is active or real knows itself adequately,
and in this self-knowledge may be supposed to pass to a greater perfection as
reflective knowledge becomes more effective and profound. For the reflective
knowledge of the mind must more and more approximate to Scientia Intuitiva
for which the, temporal transitions of Imaginatio are superseded by logical
transitions which for Scientia Intuitiva are rightly apprehended as the
eternal nisus of ground and consequents. Such concrete intuition is, according
to Spinoza, accompanied by delight proportioned to the degree of perfection already
achieved, so that acquiescentia is not, like laetitia, an unreal
abstraction or passio, but an actio, and the proper affective enjoyment
of adequate knowledge. It would be strange indeed if the mind could feel its
transition to a greater perfection and yet be wholly unaware of the perfection
itself to which it has passed; for thus perfection would be wholly relative,
instead of being the very standard of the absolute: per realitatem et perfectionem
idem intelligo (Eth. II. Def. 6). Nor can grounds and consequents be rightly
separated as successive or as co-existent in an intellectual space or neutral
▒time▓: their distinctness is not spatio-temporal, and their co-existence, though
not spatial, does not lapse into identity or confused altogetherness. It becomes
quality, and when Spinoza speaks of the possession of unchanging perfection as
being without laetitia, we must not understand him as denying that it
involves acquiescentia; rather we should assert that joy itself would
be impossible without some awareness of its termini, since though change
is not the same thing as difference simpliciter, still less is it pure
process. Awareness of change without awareness of [297] achievement or loss
is in strictness inconceivable, though the actual estimation of the result may
be vague and inadequate. Now beatitude is identical with that summa
quae dari potest Mentis acquiescentia (Eth. V. 32), which arises from the
Third Kind of Knowledge. It is the affective apprehension, not of transition
to or from perfection, but of perfection itself, not of achieving but of achievement.
But, it may be objected, the real fallacy in Spinoza▓s doctrine is not its assertion
that laetitia, or the affective perception of transition, implies acquiescentia,
or the affective perception of the termini of transition, and that hence
an eternal being is not deprived of affective or qualitative content; but the
converse assertion that there can be awareness of achievement without awareness
of achieving: that a perfect and complete being can, without change or struggle,
enjoy not merely the fruits, but also the sense, of victory. That is an objection
that seems to run nearer to the heart of the thesis, and we have to admit that
Spinoza▓s own statement about the genesis of acquiescentia in se ipso
is not altogether unambiguous. Cum fit, ut Mens se ipsam possit contemplari
eo ipso ad majorem perfectionem transire, hoc est Laetitia affici supponitur
(Eth. III. 53), which implies that acquiescentia is after all only a transition,
and therefore a particular example of laetitia. But the use of the term
supponitur is significant; for there can be no genuine transition in such
a case, for the idea and the ideae idea are one and the same: Mentis
idea et ipsa Mens una eademque est res (Eth. II. 21 Sch.). True, there
may seem to be, with the finite mind, a transition to a greater degree of reflective
clearness, arising from our ideas becoming more adequate; but this is necessarily
absent from the free mind in proportion to its freedom; and in any case it is
not a transition from knowledge of an object to reflection upon knowledge itself:
simulac enim quis aliquid scit eo ipso scit se id scire, et simul scit se
scire quod scit, et sic in infinitum (loc. cit.). Acquiescentia,
therefore, is not a transition in the same sense as laetitia, it is not
a temporal transition, but a ▒supposed▓ transition, and we must explain this
as meaning that the transition is logical rather than temporal. And it is because
the transitional nature of laetitia does not infect its qualitative content,
that perfection itself, which is no transition, may be enjoyed as quality in
acquiescentia. In laetitia the moments of temporal transition are
summed, up as enduring quality; in finite acquiescentia the moments of
logical ▒transition▓ are concretely enjoyed sub specie temporis; and in
beatitudo the eternal nisus of grounds and consequents is apprehended
and enjoyed as that intellectual love which alone among the affectus is
eternal. [298] The same distinctions are pertinent in our interpretation
of the unchanging character of the Real. The lack of transition in God is not
meant by Spinoza as an imperfection in Him, but, on the contrary, as an alternative
expression of His perfection, i.e. of the absolute completeness of His
nature. Transition is denied because it implies imperfection either in its terminus
a quo or in its terminus ad quern, in deed, ultimately in both; but
logical ▒transition▓ or nisus involves no such imperfection, but is the
very ground of all perfection, and the essence of the Real.
It is the distinction between unreal or temporal transition and
real ▒transition▓ or logical nisus (which analytically appears as feigned
transition) that makes clear the essential nature of acquiescentia and
beatitude and their relation to laetitia. Temporal transition is
unreal because it is a contradiction in terms; duration itself is only possible
as achieving grows out of achievement, and achievement out of achieving; and
in eternity achievement and achieving are reciprocal, and their reciprocity is
love: quamvis hic Amor principium non habuerit, habet tamen omnes Amoris perfectiones,
perinde ac si ortus fuisset sicut FINXIMUS (Eth. V. 33, Sch.).
Similar considerations will be found to govern Spinoza▓s conception
of the relations of change, causation, and perfection. No theory which accepted
the externality of causation could escape the objections with which we have been
dealing, for achievement would be external to the process of struggle, and could
only be recognised as achievement through our memory of the process which led
up to it. But Spinoza▓s view is that all causation is immanent or genetic in
its real nature, though, to the partiality of finite being, it may appear as
transient, and therefore as temporal. That is an inescapable fiction in the experience
of the finite self; but it need not be an error. Even the finite mind can recognise
the ultimate nature of reality, and of causation, not because it is finite but
because it is mind. Causation cannot be transient if there is to be real process
and achievement, for the memory of a process together with the perception of
its terminus ad quem could only make that end a real terminus,
an achievement, in so far as the whole process can be reviewed as a connected
whole, and not merely as a series of externally related events. The perfection
of the whole, therefore, must already contain all the stages of its achieving,
not sub specie temporis as stages external to one another and to their
end, and leading up to perfection, but sub specie aeternitatis and after
the manner in which premisses are contained in their explained conclusion.
Spinoza▓s theory of laetitia, then, must be taken as his
recognition that the finite mind perceives duration, not as [299] separated
puncta, but as quality. Pure externality belongs only to time and measure,
and these are unreal. His theory of acquiescentia, again, must be taken
as signifying that it is insufficient to establish the continuity of duration,
since it cannot be adequately perceived as pure process without termini.
It is always possession, achieving, and achievement, inextricably woven together.
Duration is only duration by the pressing in of the past upon the present and
the emergence of the future therefrom. It is not a succession of nows, it is
process; but it is not pure process, for successive positions in a real duration
are different in quality; and the essence of existence, even of enduring existence,
is that very qualitative growth through which we escape the ▒absolute relativity▓
of mere time (and the self-contradictory phrase exactly describes the logical
vice of time).
ї 5.
M. Bergson has well argued that real duration is not a kind
of space, but is an intensive quantity, i.e. a quality; the past concentrates
itself at the growing point of the present, which it permeates. And it is this
permeation of achievement or creation by possession that constitutes the reality
of duration, which is thus an enjoyed quality rather than a measurable quantity.
This conception of duration was put forward consciously as a refutation of what
M. Bergson conceived to be Spinozism, viz. the theory that causation
is identity, and duration nothing. If the view which we have put forward is correct,
the Bergsonian theory of duration is but a partial and inadequate Spinozism:
for it is not, strictly speaking, the past as past that permeates the present,
but only the past as the given, and therefore as our main source of creative
essence. The permeation of the present by the past as such could not make intelligible
the reality of duration. It becomes a miracle! What really operates is not past,
which as operating in the present is not past at all, but present; what operates
is what is equally efficient in past, present, and future, and permeates them
all, viz. eternal essence. With a stern eye directed towards M. Bergson,
Mr Alexander protests: ⌠In what sense it can be held that time as we experience
it in ourselves is other than a duration which is intrinsically successive passes
my understanding■ (Space, Time, and Deity, I. p. 124). But the implication
is not that temporal process is merely successive: or even that it is sufficient
to establish its continuity in succession. There can be no succession ▒without
change of quality, nor change of quality without permeation of some sort. But
the permeation is not that of the present by the past as such, any more than [300]
by the future as such; it is the permeation that we find in the relation of premisses
and conclusion, through which the conclusion receives its justification, and
the premisses their full content. When we say that the conclusion follows from
the premisses we do not mean that the premisses precede the conclusion in time,
but that they determine the conclusion. There may be a sense in which, on occasion,
e.g. in the process of learning, the premisses do precede the conclusion
in time, but the premisses are still premisses after the conclusion has been
drawn, and indeed, are not strictly speaking premisses at all until the conclusion
is drawn. The conclusion, again, cannot in any but the most superficial sense
be said to follow the premisses in time, since it is only a conclusion in so
far as it is determined by the premisses. Further, even where the recognition
of the conclusion follows the postulation of the premisses, it is not the premisses
alone as postulated which determine the conclusion but the system within which
the premisses operate and the conclusion remains.
Such, in spite of the analogical character of the elucidation,
is the nature of the permeation that belongs to duration. The conditions governing
abstract formal inference are necessarily an inadequate representation of real
productivity; but a perfectly adequate expression of this would pass beyond analogy
to identity, beyond abstract implication to concrete production. The creativity
of duration is one with the determination of spatio-temporal occurrence of concrete
particulars, and this again with the production by the eternal whole of its own
finite expressions or partial content. It is the nature of the whole so to express
itself and constitute itself, and since ei non defuit materia the expressions
are of all degrees of perfection, and cannot but appear, therefore, to the finite
expressions themselves, as selective and successive, i.e. as involving
limited duration. The creativity of duration, therefore, is but a finite extract
of real creativity which is eternal and constitutive. There is some danger that
in our anxiety to maintain the reality of duration, upon which all other reality
seems to, and in a sense does, depend, we may imagine either, on the one hand,
that it can be real as an unmoving and immovable hyle, or, on the other
hand, that its reality must be conceived as a creativity that ⌠passeth understanding■
and can only be met appropriately in that spirit of artificial stupidity which
is sometimes made to pass under a better name. But the reality of duration consists
in its positive quality rather than in that quantitative exclusiveness which
is its prima facie character. That positive quality is caught up into
eternity, while its externality and limitation, its negativity, is lost. In the
same way the eternal blessedness [301] of God is not a summation of the
joys of finite modes (which would necessarily be qualified by their sorrows);
it is their consummation, explanation, and infinite completion. Laetitia
is the realising of perfection in its degrees, its temporal achieving; acquiescentia
is the realisation of a perfection already achieved; beatitudo is the
realisation of perfection and its eternal achievement, it is the ideal limit
of both cupiditas and laetitia as they constitute a being for whom
transformation involves no succession. Duration only elapses in so far as the
mind drifts; for the thinking mind it ▒wells up▓; for the free man it is a ▒well
springing up into eternal life▓; and for the being that thinks all things and
is all things in their real order and efficiency, the existence which ▒wells
up▓ is eternity itself.
Further elaboration and defence of our thesis would be impossible
without proceeding beyond our present limits of space to those absorbing problems
which relate to Spinoza▓s doctrine of the eternity of the mind. We must content
ourselves with something more modest and summary, though also with something
much less than adequate. Duration, we shall say, is only a mode of imagining
the existence of things; Time is a further aid in perfecting it (i.e.,
in reducing it to absurdity); but Eternity cannot be discovered by the use of
Imaginatio but only by means of Intellectus: si quis talia ejusmodi
Notionibus, quae duntaxat Auxilia Imaginationis sunt, explicare conatur, nihilo
plus agit, quam si det operam, ut sua imaginatione insaniat (Ep. 12). And
it is because we assume, partly justifiably and partly not, that a real existence
must bear some resemblance to the existence we ascribe to the objects of sense-perception,
and which we think we understand until we try to explain it, that we rebel against
the conception of existence which we are asked to ascribe to the objects of intellect,
i.e. to real things. But the notion of existence which prima facie
we derive from sense-perception, viz. the occupation of spatio-temporal
position, is really negative; we learn nothing but that what is here-now is other
than what is there-then. But the very slightest exercise of reasoning or thought
leads us from the here-now to the there-then, and their difference is recognised
as a difference in unity and not a mere negation. Nor is their unity a mere association
or aggregation, or purely quantitative relation (for reason all the parts of
space-time are alike), it is a unity of principle which with all its differences
(and not only those given) constitutes a concrete universal determining events
in space-time, but not itself an event of the same order. So, and only so, an
enduring world is constituted, and not of located ▒nows▓. And perception itself, [302]
therefore, is only possible so far as its prima facie principles have
been transcended, and mere exclusion overcome. Further, we must recall that it
is the clear teaching of Spinoza that Imaginatio itself is not necessarily
wholly false; when, and so far as, it is taken for what it really is, it is true,
and without some transcendence of partiality and fragmentariness there would
be no perception, for there would be no content to perceive. No one has ever
perceived an event, i.e. a point-instant, or even an event-block or continuum
of point-instants. What we perceive is something occurring, i.e. the content
of space-time. What we perceive is essentially something that endures as well
as something that occupies point-instants.
Thus when the intellectual criticism of the world of perception
carries us to a world which we essentially perceive sub quadam specie aeternitatis,
we are only moving farther along the road that led to perception from impercipience.
We may freely resign ourselves to that criticism of thought already begun and
constitutive of things perceived. That criticism cannot be limited; if it applies
to the details it applies to the main business; things are as they are correctly
thought, coherently thought; and the existence enjoyed by things is to be interpreted
not by the exclusion and otherness that more obviously characterises it in the
world of perception (but could never constitute even that) but by the inclusion
and identity discovered by reason, and already enjoyed in their degree by the
partial objects of perception, and more fully enjoyed as inclusion and identity
become more full and intimate.
In duration itself, therefore, we must find the clue to the concrete
character of eternity; and though we may well admit that Spinoza passed too rapidly
from the clue to the completion, and thereby short-circuited the current of intellectual
criticism, and thus concealed the infinite content of eternity, yet we must hold
that for him duration is the limited conception, and eternity the infinite. Deo
infinita actu existentia competit... atque hanc infinitam existentiam
Aeternitatem voco (Cog. Met. II. 1). And it follows further from the clue
provided by perceptual experience, that the existence which is eternity is not
an empty form of existence, but particular existence. For it is duration that
constitutes the particular content of perceived existences, and it is eternity
itself that exists in the eternal, and is thus the very content of the Heal.
M. Bergson has made duration itself the ultimate reality, but for Spinoza
eternity is the reality of duration, and therefore the very stuff of the Real.
Quasi aeternitas absque essentiae divinae contemplatione intelligi posset,
vel quid esset praeter divinam essentiam. [303]